IF evil were anything other than the absence
of virtue it would needs be that perfection must be the attainment of evil
qualities as well as good, as that would be a part of the truest fulfilment, but
as all evil is only ever truly discerned by what it is not, it may be realised
that evil is ever an illusion, and that all fear is only of fear itself.
‘The knowledge of evil is inadequate
knowledge; hence it follows that if the human mind has none but adequate ideas,
it would form no notion of evil.’ SPINOZA.
‘In other words, if our consciousness could
expand so as to fill the infinite Universe—of course an absurd
supposition—there would be no shadow of evil in it.’ J. ALLANSON PICTON.
Bertrand Russell is very critical of this
view, which has been often propounded in the history of moral idealism. He
takes the view that cruelty for example is as positively certain a thing as
kindness. In order to be cruel one must actively seek to damage somebody. Torture,
he thinks, is a motivated and positive (or definite) deed. Torture is not the
absence of peace but the presence of violence. There is force in this
perspective, but it fails to comprehend quite Spinoza’s meaning. Take a sad
example of behaviour, a behaviour which is often observed in murderers during
their childhood: the torture of animals. Objectively speaking, and it is
difficult to view so barbarous a thing objectively, the deeds of the torturer
are not extraordinary. By this I mean, in order to hurt an animal it only
requires movement of the limbs. Some forms of torture indeed might require no
definite action at all; such are the sins of omission. Simply neglecting to
give a pet enough water or food will cause it to suffer, and if this is done
purposefully it is cruel. However, objectively the actions or omissions of two
people might be the same, though only one could be considered cruel or a torturer.
Suppose for instance that there are two owners each of a dog, and both neglect
to give their dog food or water for a week. The same amount of suffering has
been caused for each dog, but in this case only one owner has chosen not to
give his dog any food or water. The other has been laid up in hospital unable
to help even himself. So it may be observed in this that evil or harm has
been caused by a lack of action in both cases, but only the one case is
perceived as morally wrong, the other is an unfortunate accident.
This example may be tested further as an
interesting study of how mutable morality really is. Suppose in the case of the
man who is being actually cruel, and is enjoying the panting and whining of his
pet, that his dog is very fat. The fact that his dog is fat does not change the
fact that it is suffering, nor does it alter the fact that the owner is being
cruel. Yet suppose furthermore that the owner laid up in hospital has a sickly
dog that is very thin, and after a week without any nutrition it dies. Greater
evil or harm is caused by the less morally blameworthy owner than is caused by
the more morally blameworthy owner. (To remedy a possible objection let us
suppose that the owner in hospital has no friends or family and is in a coma, so
he cannot ask someone to check on his dog. It is a melancholy reflection that
such cases are not altogether rare in this highly populated world.) Can we say
this hospitalised owner has been more immoral than the cruel owner? Can we deny,
however, that the cruel owner has caused less harm to his dog?
To present some more examples, suppose a
horse kicks its owner and kills him. The owner’s friend, nearby and distraught,
shoots and kills the horse. Is this justice? Some might say, the friend is in
the wrong because he has learnt morality and the horse has not; but some others
might say, the friend had a reason for his killing and the horse had none. On
the contrary, the horse had been well looked after by his owner, and ought not
to be so unruly. It is a bad tempered horse, its violence is unwarranted. Do we
not then have a double standard? We marvel at the beauty of a lion or a tiger,
animals which will kill for no reason, purely because it is in their nature,
and sympathise with them even when they are put down; ‘they know no better’,
but equally are there not such people in the world as well? Terrible people,
people whom we dreadfully fear, who are like to these animals? Murderers can have
no reason for their crimes, almost it seems that bloodlust is in their nature;
it is unmotivated and irrational. Many animal rights protestors object to the
hunting of foxes but not to the killing sprees they go on in chicken coops.
Foxes kill for the love of it, dogs too for that matter, they will often kill
more than they can eat. Can we not give the benefit of the doubt to people as
well as to animals? If not, ought we even to give the benefit of the doubt to
animals? It is a nuisance to be such a contrarian I realise, but how can
morality be sustained if it is not tested?
Another example might be motivated cruelty
and murder. Doubtless it happens, somewhere on a remote island, or up in the
sky, certain terrorists might be tortured in order to acquire vital
information. Suppose every other strategy has been tried, the terrorists are
proud, they will not yield, so adherent are they to their cause. Let us suppose
that two terrorists knew all the details of the attacks on the World Trade
Centre in 2001, but they will not yield to cajoling, persuasion, or bribery.
Nothing else will work. Should an operative stop at this point, although he has been given
strong reason to believe that an attack might be imminent and that these
two men know something about it? Should he not have recourse to
torture? Let it be supposed that he does have recourse to torture and that he learns
of the planned attacks, that they are consequently foiled, and the lives of
3,000 innocents are saved. Was the torture moral? Rather was it not immoral and
yet had a good effect? Would the decision not to torture be moral, though it lead to mass slaughter?
I do not mean to defeat the common sense of
law and morality by picturing so many objectionable instances. Exceptions prove
the rule. Yet do we not respect the soldier who fights for our nation, our people,
and our heritage? ‘He beareth not the sword in vain.’ There is no example of evil which does not
show that evil itself is a perspective founded in worldly assumptions. Even the
most evil deeds, deeds where there can be provided no justification, is
philosophically objectionable. Take the worst kind of murderer in the eyes of
society: the murderer who has been apprised of all that is good and moral on
earth, given every opportunity for happiness and prosperity, and yet murders his
family. I struggle to conceive what in the eyes of most people would be worse,
a motive or none; whether he did it in order to receive sympathy, by casting the
blame on someone else, or simply because he felt like doing it. Suppose he sets his house on fire and receives an enormous insurance claim, and deceives the
world by pinning the blame on another, is that worse than having no reason at
all? Whichever be thought worse as showing everything that this man is not in our
eyes: not a good person, not someone who looks after his family, not
someone who thinks about others as much as himself, not trustworthy
to others, not good for society, not to be emulated by anyone
else as an example, yet we may see how right Spinoza is. Fundamentally, it is
perspective which classifies all of these things. ‘There is nothing either good
or bad but thinking makes it so.’ That does not render morality and law anything but vital and necessary to us, for it is dreadfully real to us, as real as the sun or the ground; but to God - to Ultimate Perspective - it cannot be real. From His perspective, from that of the
universe and of existence as a whole, evil is utterly subsumed and eclipsed; and beyond that eclipse: a transcendent Glory, which we should make it our entire mortal business to
conceive and to love.